By Tom Sparrow

From bookshelves overflowing with self-help books to scholarly treatises on neurobiology to late-night infomercials that promise to make you happier, more healthy, and smarter with the purchase of quite a few basic practices, the discourse of behavior is a staple of latest tradition low and high. dialogue of behavior, even if, has a tendency to overlook the main primary questions: what's behavior? conduct, we are saying, are difficult to wreck. yet what does it suggest to wreck a behavior? the place and the way do conduct take root in us? Do merely people collect conduct? What money owed for the energy or weak point of a behavior? Are behavior whatever possessed or whatever that possesses? We spend loads of time brooding about our behavior, yet hardly ever can we imagine deeply in regards to the nature of behavior itself.

Aristotle and the traditional Greeks famous the significance of behavior for the structure of personality, whereas readers of David Hume or American pragmatists like C.S. Peirce, William James, and John Dewey understand that behavior is a important part within the conceptual framework of many key figures within the background of philosophy. much less customary are the disparate discussions of behavior present in the Roman Stoics, Thomas Aquinas, Michel de Montaigne, René Descartes, Gilles Deleuze, French phenomenology, and modern Anglo-American philosophies of embodiment, race, and gender, between many others.

The essays accrued during this publication reveal that the philosophy of behavior isn't restricted to the paintings of only a handful of thinkers, yet traverses the whole heritage of Western philosophy and maintains to thrive in modern concept. A heritage of behavior: From Aristotle to Bourdieu is the 1st of its variety to record the richness and variety of this background. It demonstrates the breadth, flexibility, and explanatory energy of the idea that of behavior in addition to its enduring value. It makes the case for habit’s perennial appeal for philosophers, psychologists, and sociologists.

Show description

Read Online or Download A History of Habit: From Aristotle to Bourdieu PDF

Best humanism books

Penúltimo cuaderno: Una reivindicación de la cultura humanística

Una reivindicación de los angeles cultura humanística, asediada y cada vez más relegada hoy en día, pero que aquí recobra un sorprendente aliento, quizá porque, como cube el propio autor, se trata «de una larga tradición que se hace novedad cada vez que unos ojos los angeles existen».

Dialogue on the infinity of love, 1st Edition

Celebrated as a courtesan and poet, and as a girl of serious intelligence and wit, Tullia d'Aragona (1510–56) entered the controversy in regards to the morality of affection that engaged the simplest and most famed male intellects of sixteenth-century Italy. First released in Venice in 1547, yet by no means ahead of released in English, discussion at the Infinity of affection casts a girl instead of a guy because the major disputant at the ethics of affection.

Materialism: A Historico-Philosophical Introduction (SpringerBriefs in Philosophy)

This e-book offers an summary of key positive factors of (philosophical) materialism, in old point of view. it really is, therefore, a examine within the heritage and philosophy of materialism, with a specific specialise in the early sleek and Enlightenment sessions, best into the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. For it used to be within the 18th century that the observe used to be first utilized by a thinker (La Mettrie) to consult himself.

The Renaissance and English Humanism

The looks of a fourth printing of The Renaissance and English Humanism indicated the scholarly good fortune this booklet has loved for greater than a decade. As a quick but considerate and eloquent overview of the effect of the Christian humanistic culture upon our tradition it has no longer been handed.

Extra info for A History of Habit: From Aristotle to Bourdieu

Sample text

7. See further M. Leunissen, “Aristotle on Natural Character and Its Implications for Moral Development,” Journal for the History of Philosophy 50 (2012): 507–30. 45. See 1103a4–7, 1103a14–15, 1139a1; 1104b9, 1109a20, 1138b13–14, 1139a21, 1144b32, 1152b5, 1178a16–17. 13. 36 46. At 1144b14–15, Aristotle identifies the non-rational part of the soul which is capable of listening to reason as “ethical”; see also 1102b13–14, 1102b25–27, 1102b29–1103a1, 1138b35–1139a1, 1144b14–15. The extent to which the ethical part of the soul is rational (insofar as it is capable of being receptive to the rational part of the soul in the strict sense) has generated considerable recent scholarship.

6. Although there are passages in the Eudemian Ethics which parallel the discussions of ethos, hexis, and êthos, scholars have argued that Aristotle presents significantly different notions of the desiderative part of the soul and the stages in ethical development in the Eudemian and Nicomachean Ethics. See further H. Lorenz, “Virtue of Character in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37 (2009): 193, and A. J. London, “Moral Knowledge and the Acquisition of Virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics,” Review of Metaphysics 54 (2001): 553–54.

These verbs are related[7] to the noun consuētūdō, whose range of meanings includes habit, custom, convention, etiquette, (linguistic) usage, or a chronic condition or illness. Seneca uses this family of terms often. Dispositiō can have the sense of habit, but its use in Seneca is very rare and has the sense of orderly arrangement. The Latin noun mōs, mōris can mean custom, usage, fashion, established practice, rule, law, or ordinance in the singular. The meaning of the plural form of the word, mōres, is immediately recognizable to English speakers, and the Latin term means conduct, behavior, manners, morals, or character.

Download PDF sample

Rated 4.44 of 5 – based on 42 votes